Jump to content

Markus Hanke

Resident Experts
  • Posts

    1995
  • Joined

  • Days Won

    60

Everything posted by Markus Hanke

  1. Of course there is - it requires both a quantum channel and a classical channel. The speed is of course relative to a given observer in vacuum. The point here is that it doesn’t matter which observer you choose, the numerical value of said speed will always come out the same, ie it is invariant. Yes, I said the statistical correlation is fixed from the start (which is what ‘entanglement’ means) - I did not say that the direction of the spin is fixed. Those are not the same things at all, and they are in fact mutually exclusive, as I have already explained in some detail; you couldn’t have entanglement with a fully determined spin at the same time. I have been very explicit on several occasions about this lack of local realism. This thread is really about entanglement, not teleportation, these two being related but distinct concepts. If you wish to discuss quantum teleportation, it would be best if you opened a new thread. There is no ‘signal’ of any kind - what gives the spin direction a definite value (as opposed to a statistical probability) is the act of measuring it, meaning the process of it becoming coupled to suitable degrees of freedom of its immediate environment. Which is, of course, always a purely local process, irrespective of whether or not the particle is entangled at all.
  2. Just to add to joigus’ excellent post (+1) - spin also characterises how the mathematical object that represents the particle in question behaves under Lorentz transformations; it reflects what class of mathematical object you need to describe all relevant degrees of freedom of such a particle. Spin-0 particles are described by scalars, spin-½ particles by spinors, spin-1 particles by vectors, and spin-2 particles by rank-2 tensors. Other spins (such as 3/2 or 5/2) would correspond to multi-component spinors. These classes of objects are representations of the Lorentz group, and are valid solutions to the Bargmann-Wigner equations. Thus, spin is intrinsically a relativistic phenomenon - in a spacetime with Euclidean geometry, particles wouldn’t have spin. The elementary particles we know of have spins 0, ½ or 1; it is also possible to create composite particles with other spins such as 3/2 or 5/2. In flat spacetime, the Weinberg no-go theorem and the Coleman-Mandula theorem imply that no elementary particles with spin-3 or greater can exist.
  3. As a general reminder, I think it is wise to remember that the concepts of ‘particle’ and ‘field’ are first and foremost mathematical models - to be precise, they are irreducible representations of symmetry groups. In physics, when we say that something ‘is’ a particle or field, then the verb ‘is’ should not be understood in a strictly ontological manner, but rather in the sense that these concepts are useful models for some observable aspect of reality. They are ways to make useful and functional models of the world, not irreducible ontologies. Consider the following effects: 1. The Unruh effect: for a given volume of space, the number of particles contained therein depends on the observer. An accelerated observer will figure that the volume contains more particles than does an inertial observer, even though they are looking at the same 3-volume. 2. The Aharonov-Bohm effect: there are measurable physical effects on charges due to an electromagnetic potential, even though the charges are located in a region where the electromagnetic field is absent (F=0). So clearly, our naive intuitions of what ‘particle’ and ‘field’ might mean can be very misleading. Ultimately, the question as to what exists in an irreducible way on the most fundamental level is very much open, in physics as well as philosophy. To me, it isn’t even clear what ‘exists’ and ‘most fundamental’ actually means, since these terms would need to be defined in a completely observer-independent way, which is difficult to say the least. Modern physics takes quantum fields and spacetime to be the most fundamental categories of (physical) existence that we know of, but there is certainly no claim that there couldn’t be something else that is even more fundamental - in fact, it is quite safe to claim that there most likely will be. There are also other ways to make models of what we already know - Rovelli’s relational QM, where the central category is a network of interactions rather than a collection of entities with given properties, is a good example. With all that being said, particles and fields are far to useful as computational models in order to simply abandon them.
  4. Yes, precisely. Entanglement requires the absence of counterfactual definiteness - once the property in question can be given a definite state (no matter if we know what this state is or not), entanglement cannot exist. All these principles remain valid irrespective of the geometry of the background spacetime; even if we allow one of the entangled particles to (e.g.) fall past an event horizon, the entanglement relationship will persist. Another important observation (that may or may not have been mentioned already on this thread) is that placing a barrier between the entangled particles does not in any way affect the statistical correlation between them. This is irrespective of the precise nature of the barrier.
  5. I’m afraid I don’t have much to offer on this either. Educated guess: first of all, the mathematical form of an entangled state does not in any way depend on either the metric of the background spacetime, nor on the spatial trajectories of the particle pair. Hence I don’t see any a priori reason why simply following a geodesic path (which is what “scattering” on a BH really is) should in itself break the entanglement relationship. In order to break the entanglement, you need to interact with any part of the entangled system in a way that constitutes a measurement of whatever property has been entangled. For example, if you have a pair of particles whose spins have been entangled, then the way to break that correlation is to do something to either of these particles that allows you to figure out its direction of spin, which (if you follow the Copenhagen interpretation) “collapses the wave function”. Just scattering these particles in a curved spacetime does not itself allow you to figure out their spin directions, so in this case the entanglement should persist. By “you” I mean the environment, so by “measurement” I mean that the entangled system’s respective degree of freedom in question becomes coupled to a suitable degree of freedom in its environment. Thus, even if the two entangled particles meet again, the entanglement should persist so long as the system remains isolated from its environment. That’s my thoughts on this - someone correct me please if I’m overlooking something obvious here.
  6. Ok, so using “\langle|” and “|\rangle” is the only way to do this? Standard LaTeX has “\bra” and “\ket” commands, which is a lot more concise and convenient, but it seems these are not recognised here.
  7. \[\bra{\psi}\] \[\ket{\psi}\] \[\langle\psi|\psi\rangle\] Does anyone know a quicker way to render bras and kets (Dirac notation)? I’ve been trying the standard “\bra” and “\ket” commands, but they don’t seem to be working here for some reason. “\langle” and “\rangle” is the only alternative I can think of, but it’s a bit of a pain.
  8. It’s a very interesting approach, thanks for sharing +1 I’m definitely looking forward to seeing how this develops further, and personally I’m quite open to an approach such as this - on the other hand, extraordinary claims require extraordinary evidence, and just doing away with unitarity as a fundamental symmetry is most certainly extraordinary. So I’m open to this, but not in any way convinced.
  9. In the quantum realm, when you talk to a wall, there is a small but non-zero probability that at least some of what you say gets through to the other side: \[T^{-1} =1+\frac{V_{0}^{2}}{4E( E+V_{0})} sin^{2}\left(\frac{2a}{\hbar }\sqrt{2m( E+V_{0}}\right)\] This thread here, alas, appears to be a purely classical situation.
  10. Quantum entanglement is also a series of local events, starting from the instant when the entanglement was first created - joigus was quite right in bringing up this (classical) analogy. The difference between them is simply counterfactual definiteness.
  11. No it doesn’t - the probability of measuring either state on any of the two particles is exactly ½, and that’s a fixed probability and not a function of some distant variable. It’s both constant and invariant. There’s no meaningful sense in which you can call this an example of non-locality, because the probability isn’t a function of anything, it’s simply constant. To state this differently, there is no local experiment you can perform that will tell you whether or not a particle is entangled, because no local measurement you perform depends in any way on distant coordinates. You will always observe a probability of ½ for either local outcome of a binary state, regardless of whether the particle you perform the measurement on is entangled or not - and, more importantly, regardless of what happens anywhere else in the universe. It is only when you compare the outcomes - which you can only physically do in accord with the laws of SR - that you see the correlation. And of course, that correlation exists as the result of a purely local process in the past, which is how the entanglement came to be in the first place. If the situation were non-local, then it wouldn’t be possible to get a statistical probability of exactly ½, because the outcome would explicitly depend on some distantly variable. This is evidently not so. No you can’t, unless you already know that the particle is entangled - which you can only do if you were either present in the past when the entanglement was created, or if you bring together and compare the outcomes of measurements in the present. Both cases ensure that your prediction/correlation remains a purely local process - if neither of these local cases apply, then the probability of the distant measurement coming out in any particular way remains ½. IOW, if you don’t know whether or not a local particle is entangled, then you can’t predict the outcome of the distant measurement with certainty; and conversely, if you can predict the distant outcome with certainty, then that means the information about the pre-existing correlation is already available to you, thus ensuring that the prediction is a local process. Not only is entanglement not an example of non-locality, but non-locality and entanglement are mutually exclusive concepts! Yes, exactly - and that’s not the same as non-locality. See above, because none of the probabilities involved in the measurement outcomes is a function of distant coordinates - the correlation between outcomes exists because these particles underwent a local process in the past whereby they became entangled, and have remained that way ever since. This whole thing is a good demonstration of counterfactual definiteness, the absence of local realism, and the non-separability of specific classes of wave functions - but not of non-locality.
  12. The original Banach-Tarski “paradox” explicitly concerns a solid ball, not a sphere, in Euclidean 3-space (see first sentence): https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Banach–Tarski_paradox Not that this really makes any difference, because any 2D surface element of a sphere can likewise be considered a non-measurable ensemble of points, in which case the surface area of that subset wouldn’t be self-consistently defined either. So you could - using a similar process as in the original “paradox” - deconstruct a sphere and re-construct it in some other way, without the original surface area being conserved. There still isn’t an inconsistency, because this has to do with measures.
  13. No, it doesn’t. What it does say is that you can decompose a Euclidean 3-volume into a finite number of subsets, each of which is itself a non-measurable collection of infinitely many points, and then reassemble these subsets in a new way. The crucial point here is that you cannot uniquely and self-consistently define the notion of ‘spatial volume’ for a non-measurable infinite collection of individual points, so this decomposition does not preserve the original volume, contrary to naive intuition. It’s a subtle ‘trick’ of sorts to do with Lebesgue and Banach measures. IOW, the Banach-Tarski paradox breaks down and reassembles a 3-volume in a way that does not itself preserve the original volume. Thus it is hardly surprising that you can turn a ball into two balls in this manner - in fact you could turn a ball into anything at all in this manner, no matter how big or small. It isn’t a true paradox, and most certainly not an inconsistency in mathematics. Also, don’t forget that unfortunately we do not really live in an infinitely sub-divisible 3-dimensional Euclidean world where such a procedure could in fact be implemented - it would be a neat little trick with lots of interesting applications!
  14. Non-locality means that the outcome of an experiment/measurement performed at a specific point (be that in spacetime, or in some abstract state space) depend explicitly on what happens at another point; so the outcome is not uniquely determined by physical conditions in a small local neighbourhood alone. Consider again the example of the entangled wave function I gave earlier. The respective observable here is the probability of finding one of the particles in a specific state. For example, the local probability of finding particle A in the state ‘1’ is exactly ½; simultaneously, the local probability of finding particle B in state ‘1’ is also exactly ½. The global probability of finding state ‘10’ is 1/2, and the global probability for ‘01’ is 1/2. Neither of these probabilities is a function of coordinates - distant or otherwise -, or indeed a function of the state of the other particle. At the same time, the probability of the overall composite state to be ‘00’ or ‘11’ is exactly zero - again, without this being a function of any coordinates. At no point is any of these probabilities a function of coordinates or distant states at all, so it is meaningless to speak of this situation as being non-local. It is, however, quite meaningful and natural to speak of the overall composite wave-function as being non-separable, which is purely a stochastic statement and has nothing to do with locality. It is also an example of the absence of local realism, which is a more general concept than locality. No, that is not at all what entanglement means. Please refer back to my previous post - entanglement means that the overall wave-function of the composite system has a reduced set of possible composite states as compared to the same system sans entanglement relationships. At no point does this make any reference whatsoever to the spatial separation between these particles. Again, entanglement is purely a stochastic phenomenon to do with the form of the overall wave function, it is entirely separate from any embedding of this situation into a particular spacetime. Note also that you can entangle more than just two particles at a time, again irrespective of how far the constituents of such an ensemble are from each other. Also no. Decoherence is a purely local phenomenon - it means that local degrees of freedom of a wave function become coupled with local degrees of freedom of its immediate environment, e.g. as a result of performing a measurement. Note that the global situation - i.e. the original system plus the environment it came into contact with - remains completely coherent, and thus global unitarity remains conserved in this process, as of course it must be. For example, if you perform a spin measurement on particle ‘A’ of our entangled pair, then its spin direction becomes coupled to the mechanism of the measurement apparatus. You now have a new statistical correlation - between particle A and the measurement apparatus which it comes into contact with it, as opposed to particle A with particle B. The exchange of information involved here is thus purely local, even if the entanglement between possibly distant particles is broken in the process. Two particles being entangled fundamentally precludes the possibility of them interacting in any way after the point when the correlation has first been established, irrespective of the nature of such an interaction (FTL or not). Interacting particles cannot be entangled, since the composite wave function of such a system cannot have the form quoted earlier while still maintaining local probabilities of ½ during the measurement of the entangled property.
  15. Let’s look at this whole quantum entanglement business systematically, because I really don’t think it requires 22 pages of discussion and argument to understand this. It may be counter-intuitive, but it really isn’t that complicated. Suppose you have - to begin with - two completely separate particles, which aren’t part of a composite system; their states are thus entirely separate, and denoted by \[|A\rangle ,|B\rangle\] Don’t mind the precise meaning of this mathematical notation; it simply denotes two separate particles being in two separate states, where the outcome of measurements are probabilistic, and not in any way correlated at all. No mystery to this thus far. Now let’s take the next step - we combine the two particles into a composite system. The state function of that composite system is then the tensor product of the states of the individual particles, like so: \[ |\psi \rangle =|A \rangle \otimes |B \rangle \equiv |AB \rangle\] Again, don’t mind the precise definition of these mathematical operations; the idea here is simply that our two particles A and B form a composite system. Let’s, for simplicity’s sake, assume that each particle can only have two states, ‘0’ and ‘1’ - the physical meaning of the tensor product above is then that it combines each possible state of one particle with each possible state of the other, so the overall combined system can have four possible states: \[|00\rangle ,|01\rangle ,|10\rangle ,|11\rangle\] Thus the overall combined state of the particle pair is (I will omit the coefficients here, as the precise probabilities aren’t important): \[|\psi \rangle =|00\rangle +|01\rangle +|10\rangle +|11\rangle\] This is an example of a system that is not entangled - the combined state function can be separated into the individual states of the constituents, and all combinations are possible (though not necessarily with equal probability). Non-entangled states are separable into combinations of states of the individual constituent particles - they are tensor products of individual states - which means physically that there are no correlations between outcomes of measurements performed at the constituent particles. If you get state ‘0’ for a measurement on particle A, then you can get either state ‘0’ or state ‘1’ for a measurement on B, and these outcomes are statistically independent from each other. Mathematically, the tensor product makes no reference to the separation of the particles, ie it is not a function of their position, hence neither is the overall combined state. An entangled 2-particle state, on the other hand, looks like this: \[|\psi \rangle =\frac{1}{\sqrt{2}}\left(|01\rangle +|10\rangle \right)\] Notice three things: 1. Compared to the non-entangled state, two of the possible measurement outcomes are missing; the set of possible outcomes is reduced 2. The combined state cannot be uniquely separated into tensor products of individual states; it is non-separable 3. The form of the combined state does not depend on the spatial (or temporal) position of the particles - it is purely a stochastic statement, not a function of spacetime coordinates. What does this physically mean? Because the set of possible measurement outcomes in the overall state is reduced as compared to the unentangled case, there is now a statistical correlation between measurement outcomes - with emphasis being on the term statistical. There are now only two possible combinations, as opposed to four in the unentangled case. This is the defining characteristic of entanglement - it restricts the pool of possible combinations of measurement outcomes, because the overall state cannot be separated, due to there being extra correlations that weren’t present in the unentangled case. This is purely due to the form of the combined wave function - the outcome of individual measurements on each of the constituents is still purely stochastic, and not (!!!) a function of distant coordinates. Because the outcome (statistical probability) of local measurements is not a function of coordinates or any distant states, it is completely meaningless to say that this situation is somehow non-local, or requires any kind of interaction, be it FTL or otherwise. The entire situation is fully about statistics and correlations, which is not the same as a causal interaction; in fact, any interaction between the constituents (including FTL ones) would change the combined wave function and preclude the possibility of there being a statistical correlation while at the same time maintaining the stochastic nature of the outcomes of individual measurements. This is evident in the fact that the entanglement property of the above state function isn’t encoded in any kind of coordinate dependence, but rather in a reduction of terms, ie in a reduced pool of possible outcomes. This hasn’t got anything to do with locality at all, but is purely a statistical phenomenon. Hopefully the either helps, or possibly it might spark off another 22 pages of discussion
  16. Yes, that’s precisely my point. It is meaningless to speak of length contraction and time dilation “happening” to rulers or clocks. It’s always a relationship between two rulers, or two clocks. No. That would be like saying that a topographical map of your local area relies on an “aether” just because it uses a coordinate grid. To be sure, you can make that claim without affecting the usefulness of the map itself, if you so wish, but it doesn’t add anything to the information contained therein. Spacetime is just the same - it’s quite simply a map of events that allows you to determine separations and angles. There is no implication that we need to reify this into some kind of physical substance. This guy disagrees: Yes! Very important observation +1 This very lucidly demonstrates why a specific choice of coordinate system cannot carry physical relevance, so far as the form of physical laws is concerned.
  17. Sorry, yes. That is what I actually had in mind - I’m not used to the “ict” convention, which I haven’t seen used all too often in more modern texts. Thanks for correcting +1
  18. Such a metric would be isomorphic to the Euclidean one, and thus cannot give rise to Lorentz transformations, an invariant speed of light, or any other relativistic phenomenology. It’s precisely that - time and space parts of the metric having opposite signs - that yields relativity. Note that the choice of which part has which sign is arbitrary, so long as they are opposite.
  19. I think it is best to just keep the situation fully classic, and consider only physical clocks to begin with, rather than wave functions. The question of evolution operators in RQM is complex and very non-trivial, and does little to illuminate this underlying question. Time dilation is a relationship between reference frames, and not something that physically “happens” to a single clock. Asking for a mechanism that “slows down” some clock is thus meaningless - clocks always tick at the same rate within their own frames. So the correct question would be why inertial frames are related via hyperbolic rotations in spacetime - that’s a very valid question, but it isn’t one that any of our present theories can answer. So to make a long story short, we don’t have an explanation of why this happens, only a description of it. That’s not the same thing at all. The length of a world line between given events in Minkowski spacetime is defined to be equivalent to the proper time of a clock travelling between these events that traces out that world line. In other words, it’s simply the total elapsed time that’s physically measured on a clock that travels along a specific spatial path between events. Intuitiveness is not a necessary condition for a mathematical model to be valid and useful. It just needs to be internally self-consistent, and produce results that can be verified using the scientific method. I think you would agree that SR does this quite well. Beside, something being intuitive (or not) is a very subjective measure - many things I find intuitive might appear otherwise to you, and vice versa. I would, by and large, agree with you - though I wouldn’t put into such strong terms. I just think many depictions of physical concepts get the differences between what is an explanation and what is a description muddled up, especially within pop-sci publications. We do not yet know the underlying mechanism of why spacetime is what it is, but we do have an excellent description of its features. To fully understand why spacetime gives rise to the phenomenology we see, we’d have to figure out first how spacetime itself comes to be, and if it can be broken down further into more fundamental concepts. Such attempts are under way, but at present they are just ideas and conjectures. I disagree. Physics makes models of the world around us, but not all of these models purport to be a fundamental explanation in ontological terms. As such, SR is a very good model that is in excellent agreement with experiment and observation. It’s just important to not confuse a model with an (ontological) explanation, because they are not the same.
  20. Please define what you mean by “real geometry”? Also, the components of the metric tensor in Minkowski spacetime are real-valued, so I’m not sure what you mean by “complex metric”.
  21. There are three types of frequency shift - gravitational, cosmological, and Doppler. If you look at just one single object in isolation, then you are right in that one cannot uniquely decompose total frequency shift into these three components, based on mere observation of light received from that object. However, we don’t see objects in isolation, but an entire background of very distant objects - so we can examine them in a larger context. What we find is that there is a clear correlation between observed redshifts and distance, and that this correlation is uniform across all directions in the sky. Furthermore, we observe that all these objects recede away from each other, not just from us. This is entirely inconsistent with how gravitational redshift would work. So no, there is no contradiction - we are simply opting for the explanation that best fits the available observational data.
  22. The terminology is mostly for historical reasons, I think, though of course (at least in the case of Schrödinger) many of the physically relevant solutions to these equations are wave-like. But, as exchemist has pointed out, technically speaking they are diffusion equations.
  23. Some of these effects would be very obvious and easy to observe - for example the frequency dependence of the speed of (massive) photons. With modern telescopes we can observe objects and events at distances on the order of ~billions of LY, and for those distances the delay in arrival of photons near the blue end of the visible spectrum and ones at the red end would be on the order of months or even years. Effectively we would see high-energy photons arriving first, and lower-energy ones from the same source some ~months later. That’s evidently not what is happening. And if the effect doesn’t show up on scales of ~billions of LY, then any potential rest mass of the photon would be so vanishingly small as to be wholly unable to account for the observed DM effects (currently, upper limit for photon mass is on the order of 10^(-54)kg). The other major issue is the impossibility of having a photon mass in the presence of U(1) gauge invariance, which is an integral part of the Standard Model. If this symmetry was broken - as it would have to be in order for photons to have any mass at all - then this would have consequences not just in the EM sector, but in all the rest of the Standard Model. It’s not immediately obvious exactly what would happen in the QFD and QCD sectors, but I think it is safe to say that the Standard Model Lagrangian would need to look radically different - this isn’t just some subtle deviation that we might have missed in our particle accelerators, but more like a completely different particle zoo. Yet, the experimental data we get from our accelerators is by and large in excellent agreement with the Standard Model as it currently stands.
×
×
  • Create New...

Important Information

We have placed cookies on your device to help make this website better. You can adjust your cookie settings, otherwise we'll assume you're okay to continue.